From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

In recursion theory, α recursion theory is a generalisation of recursion theory to subsets of admissible ordinals . An admissible set is closed under functions, where denotes a rank of Godel's constructible hierarchy. is an admissible ordinal if is a model of Kripke–Platek set theory. In what follows is considered to be fixed.

Definitions

The objects of study in recursion are subsets of . These sets are said to have some properties:

  • A set is said to be -recursively-enumerable if it is definable over , possibly with parameters from in the definition. [1]
  • A is -recursive if both A and (its relative complement in ) are -recursively-enumerable. It's of note that -recursive sets are members of by definition of .
  • Members of are called -finite and play a similar role to the finite numbers in classical recursion theory.
  • Members of are called -arithmetic. [2]

There are also some similar definitions for functions mapping to : [3]

  • A partial function from to is -recursively-enumerable, or -partial recursive, [4] iff its graph is -definable on .
  • A partial function from to is -recursive iff its graph is -definable on . Like in the case of classical recursion theory, any total -recursively-enumerable function is -recursive.
  • Additionally, a partial function from to is -arithmetical iff there exists some such that the function's graph is -definable on .

Additional connections between recursion theory and α recursion theory can be drawn, although explicit definitions may not have yet been written to formalize them:

  • The functions -definable in play a role similar to those of the primitive recursive functions. [3]

We say R is a reduction procedure if it is recursively enumerable and every member of R is of the form where H, J, K are all α-finite.

A is said to be α-recursive in B if there exist reduction procedures such that:

If A is recursive in B this is written . By this definition A is recursive in (the empty set) if and only if A is recursive. However A being recursive in B is not equivalent to A being .

We say A is regular if or in other words if every initial portion of A is α-finite.

Work in α recursion

Shore's splitting theorem: Let A be recursively enumerable and regular. There exist recursively enumerable such that

Shore's density theorem: Let A, C be α-regular recursively enumerable sets such that then there exists a regular α-recursively enumerable set B such that .

Barwise has proved that the sets -definable on are exactly the sets -definable on , where denotes the next admissible ordinal above , and is from the Levy hierarchy. [5]

There is a generalization of limit computability to partial functions. [6]

A computational interpretation of -recursion exists, using "-Turing machines" with a two-symbol tape of length , that at limit computation steps take the limit inferior of cell contents, state, and head position. For admissible , a set is -recursive iff it is computable by an -Turing machine, and is -recursively-enumerable iff is the range of a function computable by an -Turing machine. [7]

A problem in α-recursion theory which is open (as of 2019) is the embedding conjecture for admissible ordinals, which is whether for all admissible , the automorphisms of the -enumeration degrees embed into the automorphisms of the -enumeration degrees. [8]

Relationship to analysis

Some results in -recursion can be translated into similar results about second-order arithmetic. This is because of the relationship has with the ramified analytic hierarchy, an analog of for the language of second-order arithmetic, that consists of sets of integers. [9]

In fact, when dealing with first-order logic only, the correspondence can be close enough that for some results on , the arithmetical and Levy hierarchies can become interchangeable. For example, a set of natural numbers is definable by a formula iff it's -definable on , where is a level of the Levy hierarchy. [10] More generally, definability of a subset of ω over HF with a formula coincides with its arithmetical definability using a formula. [11]

References

Inline references

  1. ^ P. Koepke, B. Seyfferth, Ordinal machines and admissible recursion theory (preprint) (2009, p.315). Accessed October 12, 2021
  2. ^ R. Gostanian, The Next Admissible Ordinal, Annals of Mathematical Logic 17 (1979). Accessed 1 January 2023.
  3. ^ a b Srebrny, Marian, Relatively constructible transitive models (1975, p.165). Accessed 21 October 2021.
  4. ^ W. Richter, P. Aczel, " Inductive Definitions and Reflecting Properties of Admissible Ordinals" (1974), p.30. Accessed 7 February 2023.
  5. ^ T. Arai, Proof theory for theories of ordinals - I: recursively Mahlo ordinals (1998). p.2
  6. ^ S. G. Simpson, "Degree Theory on Admissible Ordinals", pp.170--171. Appearing in J. Fenstad, P. Hinman, Generalized Recursion Theory: Proceedings of the 1972 Oslo Symposium (1974), ISBN 0 7204 22760.
  7. ^ P. Koepke, B. Seyfferth, " Ordinal machines and admissible recursion theory". Annals of Pure and Applied Logic vol. 160 (2009), pp.310--318.
  8. ^ D. Natingga, Embedding Theorem for the automorphism group of the α-enumeration degrees (p.155), PhD thesis, 2019.
  9. ^ P. D. Welch, The Ramified Analytical Hierarchy using Extended Logics (2018, p.4). Accessed 8 August 2021.
  10. ^ G. E. Sacks, Higher Recursion Theory (p.152). "Perspectives in Logic", Association for Symbolic Logic.
  11. ^ P. Odifreddi, Classical Recursion Theory (1989), theorem IV.3.22.