The set of all
Platonic solids has 5 elements. Thus the cardinality of is 5 or, in symbols, .
In
mathematics, the cardinality of a
set is a measure of the number of
elements of the set. For example, the set contains 3 elements, and therefore has a cardinality of 3. Beginning in the late 19th century, this concept was generalized to
infinite sets, which allows one to distinguish between different types of infinity, and to perform
arithmetic on them. There are two approaches to cardinality: one which compares sets directly using
bijections and
injections, and another which uses
cardinal numbers.[1]
The cardinality of a set may also be called its size, when no confusion with other notions of size[2] is possible.
The cardinality of a set is usually denoted , with a
vertical bar on each side;[3] this is the same notation as
absolute value, and the meaning depends on context. The cardinality of a set may alternatively be denoted by , , , or .
History
A crude sense of cardinality, an awareness that groups of things or events compare with other groups by containing more, fewer, or the same number of instances, is observed in a variety of present-day animal species, suggesting an origin millions of years ago.[4] Human expression of cardinality is seen as early as 40000 years ago, with equating the size of a group with a group of recorded notches, or a representative collection of other things, such as sticks and shells.[5] The abstraction of cardinality as a number is evident by 3000 BCE, in Sumerian
mathematics and the manipulation of numbers without reference to a specific group of things or events.[6]
From the 6th century BCE, the writings of Greek philosophers show the first hints of the cardinality of infinite sets. While they considered the notion of infinity as an endless series of actions, such as adding 1 to a number repeatedly, they did not consider the size of an infinite set of numbers to be a thing.[7] The ancient Greek notion of infinity also considered the division of things into parts repeated without limit. In Euclid's Elements,
commensurability was described as the ability to compare the length of two line segments, a and b, as a ratio, as long as there were a third segment, no matter how small, that could be laid end-to-end a whole number of times into both a and b. But with the discovery of
irrational numbers, it was seen that even the infinite set of all rational numbers was not enough to describe the length of every possible line segment.[8] Still, there was no concept of infinite sets as something that had cardinality.
To better understand infinite sets, a notion of cardinality was formulated circa 1880 by
Georg Cantor, the originator of
set theory. He examined the process of equating two sets with
bijection, a one-to-one correspondence between the elements of two sets based on a unique relationship. In 1891, with the publication of
Cantor's diagonal argument, he demonstrated that there are sets of numbers that cannot be placed in one-to-one correspondence with the set of natural numbers, i.e.
uncountable sets that contain more elements than there are in the infinite set of natural numbers.[9]
Comparing sets
Bijective function from N to the set E of
even numbers. Although E is a proper subset of N, both sets have the same cardinality.N does not have the same cardinality as its
power setP(N): For every function f from N to P(N), the set T = {n∈N: n∉f(n)} disagrees with every set in the
range of f, hence f cannot be surjective. The picture shows an example f and the corresponding T; red: n∈f(n)\T, blue:n∈T\f(n).
While the cardinality of a finite set is just the number of its elements, extending the notion to infinite sets usually starts with defining the notion of comparison of arbitrary sets (some of which are possibly infinite).
Definition 1: |A| = |B|
Two sets A and B have the same cardinality if there exists a
bijection (a.k.a., one-to-one correspondence) from A to B,[10] that is, a
function from A to B that is both
injective and
surjective. Such sets are said to be equipotent, equipollent, or equinumerous. This relationship can also be denoted A ≈ B or A ~ B.
For example, the set E = {0, 2, 4, 6, ...} of non-negative
even numbers has the same cardinality as the set N = {0, 1, 2, 3, ...} of
natural numbers, since the function f(n) = 2n is a bijection from N to E (see picture).
For finite sets A and B, if some bijection exists from A to B, then each injective or surjective function from A to B is a bijection. This is no longer true for infinite A and B. For example, the function g from N to E, defined by g(n) = 4n is injective, but not surjective, and h from N to E, defined by h(n) = n - (nmod 2) is surjective, but not injective. Neither g nor h can challenge |E| = |N|, which was established by the existence of f.
Definition 2: |A| ≤ |B|
A has cardinality less than or equal to the cardinality of B, if there exists an injective function from A into B.
Definition 3: |A| < |B|
A has cardinality strictly less than the cardinality of B, if there is an injective function, but no bijective function, from A to B.
For example, the set N of all
natural numbers has cardinality strictly less than its
power setP(N), because g(n) = { n } is an injective function from N to P(N), and it can be shown that no function from N to P(N) can be bijective (see picture). By a similar argument, N has cardinality strictly less than the cardinality of the set R of all
real numbers. For proofs, see
Cantor's diagonal argument or
Cantor's first uncountability proof.
In the above section, "cardinality" of a set was defined functionally. In other words, it was not defined as a specific object itself. However, such an object can be defined as follows.
The relation of having the same cardinality is called
equinumerosity, and this is an
equivalence relation on the
class of all sets. The
equivalence class of a set A under this relation, then, consists of all those sets which have the same cardinality as A. There are two ways to define the "cardinality of a set":
The cardinality of a set A is defined as its equivalence class under equinumerosity.
The
continuum hypothesis says that , i.e. is the smallest cardinal number bigger than , i.e. there is no set whose cardinality is strictly between that of the integers and that of the real numbers. The continuum hypothesis is
independent of
ZFC, a standard axiomatization of set theory; that is, it is impossible to prove the continuum hypothesis or its negation from ZFC—provided that ZFC is consistent. For more detail, see
§ Cardinality of the continuum below.[13][14][15]
Any set X with cardinality less than that of the
natural numbers, or | X | < | N |, is said to be a
finite set.
Any set X that has the same cardinality as the set of the natural numbers, or | X | = | N | = , is said to be a
countably infinite set.[10]
Any set X with cardinality greater than that of the natural numbers, or | X | > | N |, for example | R | = > | N |, is said to be
uncountable.
Infinite sets
Our intuition gained from
finite sets breaks down when dealing with
infinite sets. In the late nineteenth century
Georg Cantor,
Gottlob Frege,
Richard Dedekind and others rejected the view that the whole cannot be the same size as the part.[16][citation needed] One example of this is
Hilbert's paradox of the Grand Hotel.
Indeed, Dedekind defined an infinite set as one that can be placed into a one-to-one correspondence with a strict subset (that is, having the same size in Cantor's sense); this notion of infinity is called
Dedekind infinite. Cantor introduced the cardinal numbers, and showed—according to his bijection-based definition of size—that some infinite sets are greater than others. The smallest infinite cardinality is that of the natural numbers ().
One of Cantor's most important results was that the
cardinality of the continuum () is greater than that of the natural numbers (); that is, there are more real numbers R than natural numbers N. Namely, Cantor showed that (see
Beth one) satisfies:
The
continuum hypothesis states that there is no
cardinal number between the cardinality of the reals and the cardinality of the natural numbers, that is,
However, this hypothesis can neither be proved nor disproved within the widely accepted
ZFCaxiomatic set theory, if ZFC is consistent.
Cardinal arithmetic can be used to show not only that the number of points in a
real number line is equal to the number of points in any
segment of that line, but that this is equal to the number of points on a plane and, indeed, in any finite-dimensional space. These results are highly counterintuitive, because they imply that there exist
proper subsets and
proper supersets of an infinite set S that have the same size as S, although S contains elements that do not belong to its subsets, and the supersets of S contain elements that are not included in it.
The second result was first demonstrated by Cantor in 1878, but it became more apparent in 1890, when
Giuseppe Peano introduced the
space-filling curves, curved lines that twist and turn enough to fill the whole of any square, or cube, or
hypercube, or finite-dimensional space. These curves are not a direct proof that a line has the same number of points as a finite-dimensional space, but they can be used to obtain
such a proof.
Cantor also showed that sets with cardinality strictly greater than exist (see his
generalized diagonal argument and
theorem). They include, for instance:
the set of all subsets of R, i.e., the
power set of R, written P(R) or 2R
If X = {a, b, c} and Y = {apples, oranges, peaches}, where a, b, and c are distinct, then | X | = | Y | because { (a, apples), (b, oranges), (c, peaches)} is a bijection between the sets X and Y. The cardinality of each of X and Y is 3.
If | X | ≤ | Y |, then there exists Z such that | X | = | Z | and Z ⊆ Y.
If | X | ≤ | Y | and | Y | ≤ | X |, then | X | = | Y |. This holds even for infinite cardinals, and is known as
Cantor–Bernstein–Schroeder theorem.
^Allen, Donald (2003).
"The History of Infinity"(PDF). Texas A&M Mathematics. Archived from
the original(PDF) on August 1, 2020. Retrieved Nov 15, 2019.
^Kurt Von Fritz (1945). "The Discovery of Incommensurability by Hippasus of Metapontum". The Annals of Mathematics.